- Lecture 3 (Rebecca-Steve version): Plus Lecture 2: Section 2.4
- Welcome: But I'm still not Prof. Rebecca Martin. I just have her slides which
are the same as those of Prof. Stephen Lepp---who I also am not.
I'm Prof. David Jeffery. Just call me David---one, two, three, "David".
I'll be substituting for Prof. Lepp who is unavailable this week for lectures---but
he's still running the course via
Canvas.
- Planets known in ancient times: i.e.,
the historical planets
which included the
Sun
and Moon, but
NOT the Earth which
was definitely NOT a planet.
- What was once so mysterious about planetary motion?
- They move relative to the celestial sphere
traveling eastward near the
ecliptic.
- But sometimes they go westward in
apparent retrograde motion.
- We see apparent retrograde motion
when we pass a planet in its orbit---or in the case of
Venus and
Mercury, they pass us.
- Why did the ancient Greek astronomers
reject the real explanation of planetary motion?
- File: Star file:
parallax_stellar.html.
- The ancient Greek astronomers
knew that the lack of observable
stellar parallax
meant the Earth was unmoving
relative to the stars were extremely
far away---beyond what they thought likely.
- But why did they not think the planets
orbited the Sun
and the Sun orbited the
unmoving Earth?
They could not measure distances to the
historical planets, except
they did eventually get a good distance to the
Moon
of ∼ 60 Earth equatorial radii (R_eq_⊕ = 6378.1370 km)).
Their geometry was strong,
their instruments were weak.
- Stellar parallax is:
- Stellar parallax is: Answer.
- Section 2.4 Summary:
- Actually, lack of stellar parallax
was not the main reason, the
ancient Greek astronomers
thought the Earth was unmoving.
Like almost everyone before modern times, the main reason was because the
Earth seemed unmoving and
also seemed to be the center of
celestial axis
around which stars and
historical planets moved
but complications:
the historical planets
moving on ecliptic
relative to the stars
with, in the case, of the actual
planets
apparent retrograde motion.
- The ancient roots of science.
- In what ways to all humans use scientific thinking.
- Yours truly thinks
the trial-and-error method
(which all people use)
and scientific method
are distinct though without a hard line between them.
The scientific method
aims at general understanding through
theories, NOT just specific
recipes.
- Aside from quibbling,
astronomy
is the oldest exact empirical science,
and so the prototype
exact empirical science.
- Scientific thinking is:
- Scientific thinking is: Answer. Yours truly would add that
the understanding is via theories which
have a range of statuses.
- How is modern science rooted in ancient astronomy? Part I. A very early example at a low level.
of using the lunar phases---though
it's more than Yours truly has ever noticed.
- How is modern science rooted in ancient astronomy? Part II.
There is a rather complex story to how the
days of the week
got their names which is rooted in astrology.
See homework 4: Question 14.
- How is modern science rooted in ancient astronomy? Part III.
An obelisk can act as a crude
gnomon.
- How is modern science rooted in ancient astronomy? Part IV.
- See files in /astro/stonehenge.
- File: Stonehenge file:
stonehenge_videos.html.
- Section 3.1 Summary
- Section 3.2: ancient Greek science/nature-knowledge.
- Why does modern science trace its roots to the Greeks?
- One of the cultures that invented
philosophy
and arguably did the most in
natural philosophy.
The philosophers did dispense with mythological thinking, though much of their thinking
could be considered rational myth.
- Did scientific modeling.
- Made some progress in
mathematical physics.
- Did a fair bit of descriptive
biology,
particularly by
Aristotle (384--322 BCE)
and Theophrastus c.371--c.287 BCE).
- Did a lot of Presocratic philosophers
did a lot of fruitful speculative theorizing.
- Lots more, but you shouldn't overestimate them either.
- Ancient Greek astronomers
actually had many difficulties in planetary theory,
apparent retrograde motion
among them.
- The ancient Greek astronomers
eventually settled on
epicycle models
which maintained geocentrism
approximately
and the Earth at rest
approximately at the center of the
celestial sphere of the stars
(a real celestial sphere
on which the stars were at rest.
There was a
spherical Earth---that part was right.
The final stage of
epicycle models
in ancient Greek astronomy
was the Ptolemaic system
of Ptolemy (c.100--c.170 CE)
presented in his
Almagest (c.150 CE) as we call it.
- The Ptolemaic system:
- File: Ptolemy file:
ptolemy_epicycle_equant_animation.html.
- File: Ptolemy file:
ptolemy_system.html.
- How did the
ancient Greek astronomers
explain planetary motion.
- The the Earth at rest
approximately at the center of the
celestial sphere of the stars
(a real celestial sphere
on which the stars were at rest.
- The motions of planets
were made of compounded
uniform circular motions.
Actually, Ptolemy (c.100--c.170 CE)
violated this theory
with his equant
which he left unjustified theoretically---the
crime of Ptolemy.
- The heavens were perfect unchanging clockwork as indeed they seemed to
observations then existing, except for a few anomalies.
- How did Aristotelian cosmology
differ from
the Ptolemaic system?
- See the cartoon of Aristotelian cosmology
in aristotle_cosmos.html.
Aristotelian cosmology
hypothesized by Aristotle (384--322 BCE)
∼ 500 years before the
Ptolemaic system---but
in the telescoping of history,
they seem virtually coeval.
- How did
Aristotelian cosmology
differ from
the Ptolemaic system?
The answer and elaboration.
- Aristotelian cosmology
as the historical planets
carried by compounded invisible spheres.
See File: Aristotle file:
aristotle_cosmos.html.
The Ptolemaic system
had epicycle models.
Very different geocentric models.
- Aristotelian cosmology
was useless for making
astronomical predictions.
Aristotelians maintained
it was approximately physically correct, but nature was too complex to use
it as a calculation tool.
The Ptolemaic system
could be used to make predictions of astronomical events to reasonable
ancient accuracy.
- Aristotelian cosmology
became a philosophical dogma among people interested in
theoretical astronomy---very
few--- in
western Eurasia
until circa
1600.
The Ptolemaic system
(known only in western
Eurasia, but as far east
as India)
was regarded by many as just a calculational tool---and they were right.
- Thought question:
- Thought question: Answer, but its wrong.
Aristotelian cosmology was useless,
but the Ptolemaic system
could be used to make predictions of astronomical events to reasonable
ancient accuracy.
- Section 3.2 Summary.
- Section 3.3 The Copernican Revolution
of the 16th century
and 17th century.
- How did Nicolaus Copernicus (1473--1543),
Tycho Brahe (1546--1601),
and
Johannes Kepler (1571--1630)
challenge geocentric solar system models
of Aristotelian cosmology and
the Ptolemaic system?
- Actually, one figure shows you why
Nicolaus Copernicus (1473--1543)
proposed heliocentrism (i.e., the
heliocentric solar system):
File: Copernicus file:
venus_elongation.html.
- Heliocentrism was a radical idea.
- The Earth moved and we didn't notice:
it rotated on its axis daily and revolved around the
Sun.
In fact, it was a planet.
- The stars
were very far away because they showed no
stellar parallax
and could be other suns
spread through quasi-infinite space.
- The physics to understand
heliocentrism would
not fully exist before
the discovery of Newtonian physics
by Isaac Newton (1643--1727).
- Tycho Brahe (1546--1601).
- The Tychonic system.
- Johannes Kepler (1571--1630)
and Kepler's 3 laws of planetary motion.
- ellipse I.
- ellipse II.
- Which of the following parts of an ellipse
is a measure of its shape?
- Which of ...? Answer.
- Kepler's 1st law.
- Kepler's 2nd law of planetary motion.
- Kepler's 3rd law
of planetary motion.
- Kepler's 3rd law
of planetary motion: plot I.
- Kepler's 3rd law
of planetary motion: plot II.
- Thought Question:
- Thought Question: Answer.
- Thought Question:
- Thought Question: Answer.
- How did Galileo (1564--1642) solidify
the Copernican Revolution?
- Newton's 1st law of motion, but only sort.
Galileo did not have a perfect
understanding of it nor of
force.
- Galileo's
early telescopic observations proved
Aristotelian cosmology and
the Ptolemaic system
were both plain wrong.
And many people did accept those proofs since anyone could verify them
with a telescope.
But some did not accept them anyway.
- Galileo's discovery of jillions of
stars.
This does not prove the stars were far away, just
that most were dim.
But that they were far away and spread through quasi-infinite space
seemed very plausible.
- The Galilean moons of Jupiter
certainly orbit Jupiter, not the
Earth was not the center of
all Solar System and could
still have a moon of its own anyway.
- The phases of Venus showed
Venus orbited the
Sun.
So Aristotelian cosmology and
the Ptolemaic system
were both plain wrong.
- The Galileo affair as we call it.
The impersonal and personal aspects.
- Section 3.3 Summary.
- Section 3.4 The Nature of Science.
- The scientific method
and falsification idealized.
- How can we distinguish science from non-science?
- Hallmark 3: A scientific theory
should make testable predictions at least in principle, but it can make lots of ones
that are untestable in direct sense, but they are indirectly testable if
not dispensable by Occam's razor
and so intrinsic to all testable predictions.
The predictions can be of observations you already know, of course.
- What is a scientific theory?
Really the points cited are for an important, general, still-viable
scientific theory.
There are lots of
disproven scientific theories
and some of them were great
scientific theories that just turned out
to be wrong: e.g.,
the steady state universe.
- Question: A scientific model:
- Question: Answer.
- Thought question:
- Thought question: Answer.
Yours truly thinks D is true too aside
from pure philosophical skepticism
and as a mechanism it is mathematically absolutely true as proven
by the genetic algorithm.
- Section 3.4 Summary.
- Lecture 3a (Daniel version):
- For the mirror site,
IAL: Mirror Site
when it needs to exist.
- Welcome: But I'm still not Prof. Proga. I just have his slides.
I'm Prof. David Jeffery. Just call me David---one, two, three, "David".
I'll be substituting for Prof. Proga who is unavailable this week for lectures---but
he's still running the course via
Canvas.
- Scientific thinking:
- One basis is
trial-and-error method which
everyone has always practiced since forever.
trial-and-error alone
gives you knowledge of a
systems, NOT broad
general knowledge.
- But another ingredient is
scientific method
in which theorizing
and experimentation
are done is a cycle in idealized sense.
- A theory gives you very general
knowledge insofar as it is true.
- See sci_method.html.
- How was ancient astronomy
(the study of which is archaeoastronomy)
of use to ancient societies:
- Modestly calendrical reasons:
the motion of the
Sun on the
celestial sphere
and the phases of the Moon sufficed
for ordinary daily life.
- Observances sometimes required more elaborate
ephemerides like the
the computus.
- Divination and eventually
in some societies astrology.
- Very modestly in
navigation.
They weren't using
sextant,
nautical charts.
and
sky maps (AKA star charts).
They new certain
constellations
(NOT our modern
IAU 88 constellations)
were in certain parts of the
sky at given
times of the
solar year = 365.2421897 days (J2000).
- Wikipedia: Lunar phase:
Orientation by latitude.
- The
week
Wikipedia:
Names of the days of the week.
The classical planets
take over the rulership of the hours in the sequence
Saturn ♄,
Jupiter ♃,
Mars ♂,
the Sun ☉,
Venus ♀,
Mercury ☿
Moon ☽.
See also
Wikipedia: Planetary hours:
Table of hours,
Wikipedia: Planetary hours:
History,
Vettius Valens (120--c.175 CE) who
seems to be the in recorded history
to discuss the
planetary hours and their rulership.
- The ancient Babylonian astronomers
eventually were able to predict
eclipse phenomena using
the Saros cycle
and it lasts approximately 6585.3213 days
(see Wikipedia: Saros cycle) or
18
Julian years
(a Julian year = 365.25 days exactly
= 3.1557600*10**7 s ≅ π*10**7 s (underestimate by -0.4489 ... %)),
and 10.8213 days (i.e.,
standard metric day
= 24 h = 86400 s).
- See sundial
London sundial,
gnomon (i.e., blade),
and obelisk.
- See
Stonehenge:
The Prime Astronomical Monument.
- Machu Picchu
Wikipedia: Machu Picchu:
Intihuatana stone
Intihuatana, Urubamba.
A somewhat complicated record of
Sun ☉
lore.
- Wikipedia: Polynesian navigation
which included some
celestial navigation.
- Wikipedia: List of supernovae.
The 14th century BCE
possible supernova is NOT in the list.
- The
astronomical monuments
mostly recorded
astronomy
lore.
However,
El Caracol, Chichen Itza
may been an observatory.
See
El Caracol, Chichen Itza in Yucatan.
- See
Wikipedia: Ancient Greek science
- Aristotelian cosmology (c. 350 BCE)
(philosophical truth?)
and the Ptolemaic system (c.150 CE)
(just a calculational tool or more?)
had a long vogue in
Western Eurasia till
circa 17th century.
No one in the rest of the world had heard of them, of course.
- Eratosthenes (c.276--c.195 BCE)
and Parmenides of Elea (early 5th century BCE).
- apparent retrograde motion
- Ptolemy (c.100--c.170 CE)
Ptolemaic system (c.150 CE).
- The migration of
Greek scholars in the
Renaissance
after the Fall of Constantinople (1453)
only aided some aspects
of the Renaissance which was
had already been in progress since
c.1400 in some opinion
(see Wikipedia: Renaissance: Origins).
Renaissance astronomy
may have been helped a bit.
- Lecture 3b (Daniel version):
- For the mirror site,
IAL: Mirror Site
when it needs to exist.
- Welcome: But I'm still not Prof. Proga. I just have his slides.
I'm Prof. David Jeffery. Just call me David---one, two, three, "David".
I'll be substituting for Prof. Proga who is unavailable this week for lectures---but
he's still running the course via
Canvas.
- Nicolaus Copernicus (1473--1543) and
the Copernican Revolution:
- copernicus_portrait.html.
- Copernicus still used
epicycle model
like Ptolemy (c.100--c.170 CE).
He had to in order to make the
Copernican system predictive.
His contemporary
Renaissance astronomers
needed that in order to take the
Copernican system seriously---which,
in fact, they did as tour de force
of mathematical astronomy
though NOT of physical reality.
- ptolemy_epicycle_equant_animation.html.
- But why did Nicolaus Copernicus (1473--1543) do it?
See venus_elongation.html.
- copernican_cosmos_digges.html.
- Tycho Brahe (1546--1601):
- tychonic_system.html:
Up-to-date, but NOT too radical.
It was the
Copernican system turned on its head.
all the geometry was the same, but
Earth was
at rest.
- Johannes Kepler (1571--1630):
- Kepler's 3rd law:
It connected orbital geometry
and kinematics
and this begged for
a new dynamics
to show why.
The new dynamics turned out to be
Newtonian physics.
- Galileo Galilei (1564--1642) and the
3 overcoming of objections:
- Only for those who accepted
Galilean physics which
was NOT as complete
Newtonian physics,
and so was NOT as convincing.
- The Heavens were NOT perfect
and therefore did NOT have to have
"perfect" circular orbits.
However, Galileo himself
NEVER considered
non-circular orbits.
He NEVER assimilated the work of
Johannes Kepler (1571--1630).
Fact is, he just was NOT in
Kepler's league
as a mathematician.
- I do NOT think Galileo
overcame this objection in an empirical sense.
stellar parallax was NOT
observationally detected until
1838
by Friedrich Bessel (1784--1846)
(see Wikipedia: Stellar parallax:
19th and 20th centuries;
Wikipedia: Friedrich Bessel: Work).
Galileo's work probably
did make it seem a less important objection and
by circa 1700 most
astronomers probably did
NOT think it an important objection at all.
- I think this is a bit of a fine point of argument.
Galileo
showed that stars
stayed point-like in the
telescope
which meant they were much farther than
planets OR much smaller.
The former is true, but Galileo
could NOT prove that.
Of course, if you believed the
stars were other
Suns then they
were far away and the lack of OBSERVABLE
stellar parallax
was NOT an objection to
heliocentrism.
- The discovery
of the Galilean moons
of Jupiter ♃:
- Proved Aristotelian cosmology
and the
Ptolemaic system
did NOT know everything about the
cosmos since
they did NOT know about the
Galilean moons.
- Proved the
Earth was NOT
unique center of motion as in
Aristotelian cosmology
and the
Ptolemaic system,
and so they were WRONG about that.
- It suggested (but did NOT prove) that
smaller
astro-bodies
had to orbit larger
astro-bodies
relative to the
fixed stars.
If so, the Earth
had to orbit
Sun and NOT
vice versa
relative to the fixed stars
as SEEN from another
astro-body
moving slowly relative to the
fixed stars like
like Jupiter ♃ itself
or a fixed stars.
Recall, from the
Earth's
perspective, the
Sun does geometrically orbit
the Earth.
But we consider this a geometrical orbit since it is NOT
relative to the
center of mass
of the Solar System
in Newtonian physics.
But this perspective was NOT available to
Galileo's
contemporaries, and so how exactly to decide the argument then was NOT clear I think.
If you were already a convinced
heliocentrist, then
you already had a consistent
theory of what
orbits what
in a physical or causal sense.
- The phases of Venus
proved Aristotelian cosmology
and the
Ptolemaic system
were just plain WRONG.
Venus in a direct sense
orbited
the Sun.
But this was consistent with the
Tychonic system
as well as
heliocentrism.
- So much is known of the
Galileo affair
that I won't say much about it.
In fact, UNLV has a great expert on it,
Maurice A. Finocchiaro, UNLV
Distinguished Professor Emeritus who has written
The Galileo Affair
1989.
- This has to be qualified.
The work of Galileo,
Johannes Kepler (1571--1630),
and others EVENTUALLY made
heliocentrism
the most plausible
theory of the
Solar System to
most of those interested in astronomy.
To prove heliocentrism
in the context of a physical theory, it had to be proven by that
physical theory.
This proof was given
Isaac Newton (1643--1727)
in his book
Philosophiae
Naturalis Principia Mathematica (Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy") (1687)
which presented what we
call
Newtonian physics.
However, Newton
probably believed
heliocentrism
ever since he learned anything about
astronomy since
all of his teachers did.
Newton would have
been surprised if
heliocentrism had turned
out to be WRONG.
- The scientific method.
- These statements are in the realm of
philosophy of science
and NOT everyone would agree with them or would agree only with
qualifications:
- For example, yours truly believes some theories are so well
established that they are correct/true within the range of validity aside
from pure
philosophical skepticism,
Newtonian physics
for example.
- Occam's razor is a useful
rule, but you have to make a judgment about "simpler" and different some people
might make different judgments.
Also some might say, particularly about profound theories, that "simpler" is NOT
the right comparison tool.
For example, consider the
comparison between the
Aristotelian cosmology,
the Ptolemaic system,
the Copernican system,
and the Tychonic system.
There were so many dimensions to the comparison in circa
1600 that it was hard to say
which was "simpler" or whether "simplicity" was the right comparison tool.
Or for another example, in most respects
people would say Newtonian physics
is simpler than the
theory of relativity (meaning
both special and generality), but
even before any there was any ordinary evidence preferring
theory of relativity,
a very insightful person might say
the theory of relativity
is to be preferred since it answers questions which have
NO answers in
Newtonian physics.
- Most people would agree with this statement, but with qualifications.
One is that observations/experiments can
be faulty.
In some cases, it takes a long time for
a theory to be proven wrong.
There are other objections too.
- A key objection by yours truly.
A scientific theory
is still a scientific theory if it has
been proven wrong: it's then a wrong
scientific theory.
Actually, wrong scientific theories
can be brilliant and educationally useful, and they might later prove to right with some
changes.
- Yours truly agrees with (c), but
in a nuanced sense yours truly believes (d) too.
-
Again scientific theories
are still scientific theories
even if they are wrong.
- Astrology.
- Horoscopes:
- Johannes Kepler (1571--1630).
- brutus_james_mason.html.
- Galileo
dispelled, but not totally dispelled.
- Some people in
the 16th century did hope the
Copernican system
would make better predictions.