html>
We discuss it in here in IAL 0 because it's a bit philosophical and does NOT fit anywhere else in IAL.
The term anthropic principle was coined in 1973 though the idea of such a thing goes back to 1904 (see Wikipedia: Anthropic principle: Origin) and perhaps earlier in a vague sense.
The anthropic principle has been controversial: some argue that it is trivial or worthless as a scientific prinicple.
Part of difficulty in assessing the value of anthropic principle is that there are different versions of it, and so its value is version dependent.
However, it seems a basic anthropic principle has gained traction and is of some importance in modern astronomy and physics.
Put as an aphorism, the anthropic principle states:
An explication anthropic principle
that seems generally acceptable is as follows:
Some conditions of the
observable universe
have to exist or there would be NO observers to observe them.
That there are observers is a partial explanation for those conditions.
The observers can be specified in different ways:
However, most people it seems choose
life as we know it, and
so "biotic priniciple" would be a better name than
anthropic principle.
The reason for choosing life as we know it
is that life as we know it
seems to be ineluctable in the
observable universe
(unlike humans who are obviously
eluctable)
and specifying the necessary conditions for
life as we know it
seems a lot easier than for technologically advanced intelligent
life as we know it
or intelligent life as we know it.
The 5th catetory seems to be broad to be interesting.
The
anthropic principle
would obviously be very useful if allowed you to discover something about the
observable universe
that you did NOT know before---it would then be a DISCOVERY TOOL
For example, you had never noticed A, but then you realized there had to be A
for life as we know it to exist
and then you looked for A and discovered it.
But that the anthropic principle
has ever been a DISCOVERY TOOL in any important way is controvsial.
section UNDER RECONSTRUCTION BELOW
For yours truly and many others,
the most important
anthropic principle
possible discovery is of
multiverse.
The theory
of the multiverse
itself branches into quasi-infinite varations, but one version
in short it is the idea that
there are other realms of existence where the
laws of physics
differ from those of the
observable universe.
These other realms may be just far away in
space outside of the
observable universe
or maybe far away in time
or both or
just detached from observable universe
An possible
argument from the anthropic principle
for the multiverse
goes as follows:
Say you have events A and B and
On the other hand, you know nothing about B if A does NOT exist.
It could exist or NOT.
And P(A|B) (i.e., probability of A given B) is also unknown.
The equation P(B|A) = 1 is the general essence of
the anthropic principle.
It applies to anything.
A does NOT have to be humans
or living beings at all.
The essence of the
anthropic principle is
"we" (and "we" in general is anything existing) is A
and if P(B|A) = 1, then B must exist.
In other words, A exists implies B exists.
What's B? Any of a vast number of things that are necessary for A to exist.
We give one famous example of B below in subsection
Anthropic Principle Example:
The Triple-Alpha Process.
What's A?
There are many possibilities.
Possible A values relevant to
human
(which are the ones usually considered when discussing the
anthropic principle)
roughly in order of increasing generality are:
Interestingly, there is historically a forerunner of
the anthropic principle
in Aristotelianism.
To explicate,
Aristotelianism considers
A to be
a final cause of B
since B exists, among other things, to make A possible.
This Aristotelian
teleological point of view
is useful in some contexts (e.g., things designed by
intelligence or
evolution),
but probably NOT many others.
An example
from evolution is that
animal flight (i.e., A)
is the final cause
of wings (i.e., B).
But, of course,
wings can and do exist without
animal flight.
However,
wings used in or once used in
animal flight
did evolve the way they did
for animal flight.
In the subsection below, we give a famous example of the
application of the
anthropic principle
used as a discovery tool.
There were more examples once, but enough is enough.
Probably the most famous example of the use of
anthropic principle
was in the
discovery of the
triple-alpha process
in 1952.
Recall, the term
anthropic principle
was coined in 1973.
So only retrospectively has the term been applied to this
discovery.
The story in
point form:
In 1953,
the Big Bang theory
(then very rudimentary compared to today)
and the steady state universe
were considered the most---maybe the only---viable
cosmological models.
In other words, an
anthropic principle argument
argued for
the triple-alpha process---and,
as aforesaid,
this was before
the expression anthropic principle
was coined in 1973
(see Wikipedia: Anthropic principle: Origin).
The properties of the winners of a
lottery are quasi-unique
due to random peculiarities, but there
are always winners
of a lottery.
What if A exists, but P(B|A)∈(0,1).
Now you only know that B could exist.
You could still search for B if P(B|A) is estimated to be large enough for the
search to be worthwhile.
The formula
P(B|A)∈(0,1) can be called
the extended (general)
anthropic principle.
Searches for B given P(B|A) siginificant probably go on all the time
without bother to use the name
anthropic principle.
The subsections above show that yours truly's
opinion that the
anthropic principle
is a useful
scientific prinicple
in both explaining in a sense why things are as they are and sometimes as a
discovery tool.
There are criticisms of the
anthropic principle
(Wikipedia: Anthropic principle: Reception and controversies),
but yours truly thinks those
are mostly directed toward more extravagant claims for it than those discussed here.
In IAL,
we occasionally refer to the
anthropic principle.
php require("/home/jeffery/public_html/astro/art/art_o/orson_welles_chimes_at_midnight_a.html");?>
The above argument is just an example of the kind of arguments from and over the
anthropic principle.
      P(B|A) = probability of B given A = 1    ,
then B must exist if A exists.
php require("/home/jeffery/public_html/astro/atomic/periodic_table.html");?>
php require("/home/jeffery/public_html/astro/atomic/nuclear/triple_alpha_process.html");?>